Precedent: Porovnání verzí
(Značka: editace z VisualEditoru) |
(Značka: editace z VisualEditoru) |
||
Řádek 11: | Řádek 11: | ||
Lords decision. (Cf. also Duke v. Reliance Systems Ltd. (1988) Q.B. 108, | Lords decision. (Cf. also Duke v. Reliance Systems Ltd. (1988) Q.B. 108, | ||
113). (s. 326, Interpreting Precedents, United Kingdom) | 113). (s. 326, Interpreting Precedents, United Kingdom) | ||
+ | |||
+ | However, 'leading cases' as such have really no special authority | ||
+ | |||
+ | as precedents; they are features of the doctrinal evolution of law as | ||
+ | |||
+ | much as of the doctrine of precedent itself. (s. 341, Interpreting Precedents, United Kingdom) | ||
=== Filozofické pozadí precedentu === | === Filozofické pozadí precedentu === |
Verze z 22. 10. 2017, 09:40
Jeden z důvodů, kdy není nutné následovat precedent:
per incuriam, or when a case had been impliedly overruled by a later House of Lords decision, or where there was a conflict between two Court of Appeal judgments. This means that it will not be bound by decision reached in ignorance of relevant statute law, or relevant and binding prior precedent of the Court of Appeal or the House of Lords, or unless the precedent had been expressly or impliedly overruled by a subsequent House of Lords decision. (Cf. also Duke v. Reliance Systems Ltd. (1988) Q.B. 108, 113). (s. 326, Interpreting Precedents, United Kingdom)
However, 'leading cases' as such have really no special authority
as precedents; they are features of the doctrinal evolution of law as
much as of the doctrine of precedent itself. (s. 341, Interpreting Precedents, United Kingdom)
Filozofické pozadí precedentu
Historically, there have been two principal rationales for precedents
having the kind of status that they have in our system. These
are the declaratory theory and the law-making theory of precedent.
A third view discernible in modern times, but with ancient roots,
might be called the 'determinative theory'.
The declaratory theory represents precedents as evidence of the
law, rather than constitutive of it. The law is conceived as a body of
principles about rights and duties and the like. It is implemented
only partially in statutes, and carried into effect by judicial decisions. (s. 330, Interpreting Precedents, United Kingdom)
This is
especially so where there has grown up a line of decisions on similar
topics in similar tenor. But the law itself is only evidenced and
declared by, not made by, these decisions. (s. 330)
This doctrine of the independent existence of law presupposes an
appropriate ontology for law, and this was supplied by either a
theory of rationally evident natural law or a theory of law-as-custom,
especially as 'learned custom'. Quite often, indeed, the natural law
and the custom view were presented as mutually supportive and
even logically linked. (s. 330)
What is important in the declaratory approach is that it is essentially
custom that gives the rationale for precedent since this gives us
a reason for doing 'what we have always done' as being evidence for
some deeper truth (the will of God or the best way of going about
things). (s. 331)
Teorie soudcovské tvorby práva
Judicial law-making theories start from a denial of the natural law
premises of the declaratory theory. A basic tenet of legal positivism is
that all law derives from authoritative decision, hence all human law
from authoritative human decision. There is no essence of law beyond
or behind what is decided as law by some competent decision
maker. From this it follows obviously that, if precedents are evidence
of the law, they can be so only because judges are accorded authority
to make law through their decisions. Conversely, the very recognition
of precedent as evidence of the law amounts to recognition of
the power of the courts to make law. (s. 331)
Jeremy Bentham, father of
English legal positivism, was particularly strong in his denunciation
of the declaratory theory as a form of mystification of law, hiding the
power of 'Judge and Co', and insistent on recognition of the fact of
'judicial legislation' through precedent. His followers, from John Austin
through to H.L.A. Hart, though less critical of judges and of the
common law than Bentham, retain firmly the view that precedent is
a 'source of law' in the sense that judicial decisions are constitutive
rather than declaratory of law. (s. 331)
During the nineteenth century, and into the twentieth century, the
positivistic view strongly predominated in the legal thought of the
UK. This had considerable impact on the practice of the courts in
relation to precedent, in two ways. First, there was a tendency to ever
stricter doctrines of binding precedent, and to hierarchically ordered
rankings of binding precedent, on the ground that this recognized the
fact of judicial law making, but kept it to a minimum while establishing
a rational hierarchy of interstitial legislative authority among the
courts. Second, there was a considerable theoretical focus on trying to
find exact ways of identifying the rules created by precedents, hence
much focus on elucidations of the idea of the ratio decidendi. (s. 332)
Determinative Theory
The modern stress (cf. Dworkin, 1978; 1986) is on law as grounded
in principles partly emergent from practice and custom, partly constructed
out of moral or ideological elements that bring together
practice and contemporary values in a coherent order (MacCormick,
1984). Legal rules and judicial rulings on points of law are then to be
understood as 'determinations' (in the Thomistic sense) of background
principles - neither simple deductions from them nor arbitrarily discretionary
decisions about them, but partly discretionary decisions
as to the best way of making the law determinate for a given (type
of) case (Finnis, 1985). From this, the best present day rationale of
precedent would seem to be what we would call a 'determinative
theory', which can well account for the continuing role of judicial
precedent as a 'source of law', but a defeasible one. (s. 332)
Doctrines like the 'determinative theory' which suggest a more holistic
approach to legal systems or, more likely, to particular branches of
law, favour the development of a strong sense of underlying principles
proper to particular fields and branches of law, and the taking of
a coherent view of legal doctrines as congeries of principles, values
('policies') and their determination through decision making which
is truly sensitive to the full particularity of contexts of decision. (s. 334)
Tento článek je příliš stručný nebo postrádá důležité informace. Pomozte naší wiki tím, že jej vhodně rozšíříte. Nevkládejte však bez oprávnění cizí texty.